Pengikut

Sabtu, 29 Oktober 2016

A Structural Analysis Of Thinking




It is time now to discuss in more detail the structure basis for thinking in general. As we have already noted, information is obviously recorded is some manner of other in the mind-brain sytem. Although “nerve cell” details are relatively sparse as to how such material is actually recorded, it is reasonable to assume that the information is somehow coded into a structure which is in turn represented by a nerve structure. The mind-brain construct is often referred to as a mental structure. The term can mean either the associated concrete nerve structure or the abstract structure that represents it. Observe that the second point of view focuses more attention on the structure concept. For this reason, we usually think of a mental structure as an abstract entity.
As was already mentioned, our assumption is that the thinking process is one of the special function of the general structure processing activity of the human brain, and the material of thought consists of the information recorded as tructures in one’s mind-brain system. This material consist of ideas and concepts; cinther structures extracted from current sense data, or retrieved from previously recorded information.
Despite the difficulties of determining just how structures are generally recorded of coded in the brain, a very important and better known intermediate device involves the use of language in any form. In this case, a structure is represented by language structure that involves time. In other words, the structure is presented piecewise and strung out in time. This form of representation is of special importance because is provides a mechanism for communicating the content of a structure from one person to another (deSaussure, 1966; see Rickart 1995, chapter 5). From our point of view, use of language is only one among many special ways that structures may be manipulated. In other words, thinking is a remarkable tool for dealing with mental structures but is generally independent of language, although the possibility of communication provided by language is of an unquestioned special importance.
Thinking, with or without language, invlovesideas or concepts directly in terms of their basic intrinsic relationship. They are somehow represented so that they can evolve and interact, largely independently of the outside world. The system may, of course, use material out of memory banks and even occasional inputs from the outside. In this context, language becomes just another method of manipulating structures. Although thinking is normally independent of language, it may shift into the communication mode, if needed.
Language can play a very important positive role in thinking, but it can also play a seriously negative role. For example, it is possible for language to function quite independently of underlying ideas for which it was ostensibly created. It is, of course, by virtue of its structure that language is able to represent a system of ideas. At the same time, the language structure may exist independently of idea structures that is usally organizes. When thins separation occurs, the underlying substance idas may be lost and we are left with the empty language it self. Everyday examples of this are found, for example, in the use of clichés. We see it in mathematics when the formalism is used without the underlying mathematical ideas. In other words, the structure of the formalism is adopted for its own sake. This comes up again later, when we examine, for example, some of the problems associated with the teaching of elementary algebra.
Despite our insistence that thinking is not dependent on language, there are some who maintain that all thinking is actually self-communication, and thus is dependent on language in some form or another. Although this point is obviously dependent on ones definition of thinking, the language restriction would exclude many instances of mental activity that, in my opinion, should be classified as genuine thinking. Included, for example, are certain mental experiences of any creative mathematician. I offer specific examples later.
Thinking is generally regarded as taking place in the conscious part of the mind. However, again because of some rather vivid mathematical experiences, plus certain other ordinary phenomena, it appears that there does not exist a sharp distinotion between the conscious and un conscious thinking. The process can evidently take place in either the conscious or unconscious mind and even shift back and forth between the two. What is missing when the unconscious is involved is the monitoring or censoring of the whole process by the conscious. The unconscious setting, despite a lack of discipline, may allow a freedom of mental activity that can be far more creative than when restricted by the conscious. Illustrative examples are presented later.
At this point it is important to make a distinotion between the general unconscious, which we have in mind here when we refer to the unconscious, and the Freudian unconsciousness. There is not a sharp line dividing the general unconscious and the conscious mind. Although there are regions in the general unconscious that are not easy to success, much of it is very close to the conscious so that passage between the two is not difficult. This is not the case with the Freudian unconscious, which is difficult to access and is normally widely separated from the conscious. Any influence that it has on mathematical thinking is probably limited to familiar Freudian phenomena, which are not easily related to the highly rational mental phenomena characteristically associated with mathematical thought.

Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar